court case current events politics

The Courts’ Role in Political Gerrymandering

December 4, 2019 | Yuwen Wang

Edited by: Allison Li

Legislative apportionment—the distribution of representation among the constituencies of a representative body—is largely conducted by state legislatures. Consequently, it is subject to the influence of the current majority political party, producing a map of districts favoring that party. This practice, known as gerrymandering, has grown increasingly intricate and potent due to technological advancements that maximize the electoral advantages of the party controlling the redistricting process, thereby minimizing the voices of voters belonging to the minority party. In spite of this handicap to American democracy, the Supreme Court of the U.S. has repeatedly failed to strike down severely politically-gerrymandered districting plans. In the latest 2019 case of Rucho v. Common Cause, the SCOTUS held that partisan gerrymandering is a non-justiciable issue, likely setting a precedent for courts across America to reject hearing similar cases. 

The plaintiffs in Rucho claimed that North Carolina’s 2016 congressional map was a product of unconstitutional partisan gerrymandering in violation of the First Amendment, the Equal Protection Clause, and Article I sections 2 and 4 of the U.S. Constitution.[1] In a 5-4 majority opinion written by Chief Justice Roberts and joined by Justices Thomas, Alito, Gorsuch and Kavanaugh, the Supreme Court held that partisan gerrymandering is a non-justiciable issue. Citing the lack of a consistent and clear standard to differentiate between constitutional and unconstitutional gerrymandering, Chief Justice Roberts asserts that partisan gerrymandering is a political question outside the reach of federal courts.[2] Courts avoid adjudicating on political questions on the assumption that doing so would plunge the justice system into the “political thicket,” a phrase that originated from Supreme Court Justice Frankfurter in the case Baker v. Carr, damaging the impartiality of the courts.[3]

The issue of legislative apportionment was first determined to be within the jurisdiction of federal courts in 1960 case of Baker v. Carr. The central question in Baker was similar to that of Rucho: “Does the Supreme Court have jurisdiction over questions of legislative apportionment?”[4] But unlike the Roberts court in Rucho, the Warren court in Baker found that apportionment did not present a political question and was thus justiciable. In his plurality opinion joined by Justices Warren and Black, Justice Brennan considered six factors of the political question doctrine that, if present, would compel the Supreme Court to withhold its opinion [5]

  1. A textual constitutional commitment of the matter to another branch of government, such as the power of the President in foreign affairs;
  2. A lack of judicially discoverable and manageable standards for resolving the issue;
  3. A need for an initial policy determination before addressing the matter that courts would not be able to reach;
  4. A situation in which independent court action would violate the separation of powers framework;
  5. An unusual need to strictly adhere to a previous political decision; or
  6. A possibility that clashing statements on an issue by multiple branches of government would cause embarrassment.

 While Justice Brennan held that the issue of population inequality in Baker did not contain any of these factors, Justice Roberts argues that the issue in Rucho does: there is “a lack of judicially discoverable and manageable standards for resolving” partisan gerrymandering.[6] The claim of population inequality in Baker v. Carr could be decided under the Equal Protection Clause, using standards which the Court deemed to be “well developed and familiar.”[7] Claims of racial gerrymandering could be decided under the Voting Rights Act, using the criteria the SCOTUS developed in Thornburg v. Gingles (1986).[8] However, unlike other legislative apportionment issues such as population inequality and racial gerrymandering, partisan gerrymandering lacks clear and uniform judicial standards. 

The plaintiff in Rucho hinged the claim of unconstitutional partisan gerrymandering upon the First Amendment, the Equal Protection Clause, and Article I §2 and §4 of the Constitution, none of which provides clear or “manageable” standards acceptable to the Supreme Court. The Roberts opinion in Rucho rejects the test used by District Courts to evaluate claims of partisan gerrymandering on the basis of the First Amendment; it asserts that the test does not “distinguish permissible from impermissible partisan motivation.”[9] Moreover, no viable standard for political gerrymandering has emerged under the Equal Protection Clause in a span of nearly 18 years; the Supreme Court failed to reach an appropriate solution to political gerrymandering using Equal Protections in both Davis v. Bandemer (1986) and Vieth v. Jubelirer (2003).[10] The plurality opinion in Vieth also determined that neither Article I, §4 nor Article I, §2 “provides a judicially enforceable limit on the political considerations that the States and Congress may take into account when districting.”[11] The dismissal of all four legal bases in the case of Rucho as “judicially discoverable and manageable standards” rendered the claim to be non-justiciable. Though partisan gerrymandering poses a growing threat to the constitutional rights of political minorities in various states, the lack of rigorous standards for distinguishing an unconstitutional partisan gerrymander from a constitutional one has deterred the Supreme Court from properly addressing this threat. 

If the issue with adjudicating partisan gerrymandering cases lies within discerning constitutionality, it begs the question of whether the Supreme Court can simply declare all political gerrymandering to be unconstitutional. The Supreme Court held that “a jurisdiction may engage in constitutional political gerrymandering” in Hunter v. Cromartie (1999).[12] When the Framers drafted the Constitution, they acknowledged and allowed the existence of political bias in redistricting. Article 1, Section 4 of the Constitution states that “the times, places and manner of holding elections for senators and representatives shall be prescribed in each state by the legislature thereof.”[13] As the framers deliberately gave the power of drawing political maps to the state legislature, they certainly anticipated the political majority to heavily influence this process. This election clause seemingly enshrines political gerrymandering in the U.S. Constitution, yet it is imperative to understand that the framers’ idea of legislative apportionment took on a far cruder form than what it has become today. So while the framers technically condoned political gerrymandering through this clause, they certainly could not have foreseen how it has evolved alongside redistricting technology. 

In her dissent in Rucho, Justice Kagan reflects this sentiment by asserting that today’s mapmaking technology has made “gerrymanders far more effective and durable than before, insulating politicians against all but the most titanic shifts in the political tides.”[14] The adverse effects of modern gerrymandering on fair partisan competition are evidently deteriorating the democratic ideals the framers intended for the Constitution to safeguard. So while the dictum in Hunter v. Cromatie does follow the letter of the law, allowing partisan gerrymandering to freely assail democratic competition does not reflect the spirit of the law. This decision blatantly contradicts the Supreme Court’s duty to reinterpret the Constitution, a duty that is especially pertinent in an America marked by political polarization and a breakdown of institutional forbearance as both political camps stretch the letter of the Constitution to maximize their self-interest. To address this, the Supreme Court must curtail political gerrymandering as a whole, or construct usable judicial standards that draw a distinct line between the constitutional kind and the unconstitutional kind.

To explore the option of eliminating all forms of political gerrymandering, it could be instructive to look to states with independent commissions handling legislative apportionment—such as California. First established in 2010 after a narrow win on the state ballot, California’s Citizens Redistricting Commission is an agency dedicated to fair redistricting. After a complex selection process, five Democrats, five Republicans, and four members belonging to neither party were ultimately chosen to serve on the commission.[15] Nonetheless, this seemingly fair approach to redistricting is not safe from partisan manipulation. The Californian Democratic party has allegedly enlisted lobbyists, trade unions, and other special interest groups to pose as ordinary voters as to surreptitiously influence the map drawing process.[16] Rather than eliminating partisan gerrymandering, the establishment of this independent commission simply rendered it less detectable. Disregarding the clear flaws of a system such as California’s, it is also highly unrealistic that the current Supreme Court would vote to end all political gerrymandering. This act of imposing federal will onto state legislatures not only breaches the election clause, but will also elicit terrific backlash as states wrestle to preserve the power of dictating their legislative apportionment.

If outlawing all forms of political gerrymandering is unrealistic to pursue at the federal level and difficult to implement at the local level, we must return to devising a usable standard to judge its constitutionality. To this end, the courts should consider the efficiency gap, a measurement of wasted votes, conceived by Nicholas Stephanopoulos, a University of Chicago professor, and Eric McGhee, a Californian political scientist.[17] The efficiency gap is equivalent to the difference between the two parties’ wasted votes in an election divided by the total number of votes cast. To transform this metric into a court doctrine, Stehphanopoulos proposes an efficiency gap threshold of two seats for congressional plans and 8 percent for state house plans to determine constitutionality.[18] Critics of the efficiency gap standard argue that it too simplistic to address the multifaceted nature of legislative apportionment. For example, in states where Democrats are concentrated in cities, the efficiency gap threshold would deem the districts drawn to be unconstitutional gerrymandering.[19] Acknowledging this, Stephanopoulos emphasizes that the threshold he proposes should not be the only element of a judicial doctrine for political gerrymandering; states would be able to  defend the constitutionality of their district maps by proving that their large efficiency gaps are results of natural political geography.[20] While the efficiency gap has undeniable flaws, it remains a valid tool that, with some refinement, could yield a usable judicial doctrine. A U.S. District Court successfully utilized the efficiency gap standard laid out by Stephanopoulos to strike down Wisconsin’s redistricting scheme as unconstitutionally partisan in Gill v. Whiteford.[21] Though this standard has not yet been applied at the federal level, it is a metric of partisan symmetry that potentially satisfies the “judicially discoverable and manageable standards” demanded by the SCOTUS.

In the face of a democracy eroded by political polarization and nefarious partisan manipulation, the Supreme Court must reexamine the costs of its avoidance of partisan gerrymandering. The increasingly adverse effects of partisan influence on redistricting should not be ignored simply because no viable and uniform judicial standard currently exists. The precedent of nonintervention in fear of the “political thicket” set in Rucho is unconducive to combating this breach in our democratic institutions. In an era where a demagogic president and a polarized legislative branch fail to maintain partisan tolerance, the Supreme Court must undertake this duty, for ensuring that every American can exercise the right to participate in truly fair and competitive elections is protecting the very heart of our democracy.


Citations

[1] Rucho v. Common Cause,  588 U.S. ___, 1 (Syllabus). 

[2] Ibid., 11 (Robert’s opinion).

[3] Baker v. Carr, 369 U.S. 186 (1962).

[4] Ibid.

[5] Ibid.

[6] Rucho, 11 (Robert’s opinion).

[7] Baker.

[8] Thornburg v. Gingles, 478 U.S. 30 (1986).

[9] Rucho, 27 (Robert’s opinion).

[10] Vieth v. Jubelirer, 541 U.S. 267 (2004).

[11] Ibid., 6. 

[12] Hunt v. Cromartie, 526 U.S. 541 (1999).

[13] U.S. Const. art. 1, § 9.

[14] Rucho, 10 (Kagan’s dissent).

[15] “California Citizens Redistricting Commission.” Ballotpedia. Accessed November 9, 2019. https://ballotpedia.org/California_Citizens_Redistricting_Commission.

[16] Pierce, Olga, and Jeff Larson. “How Democrats Fooled California’s Redistricting Commission.” ProPublica. Pro Publica Inc., December 21, 2011. https://www.propublica.org/article/how-democrats-fooled-californias-redistricting-commission.

[17] Cameron, Darla. “Here’s How the Supreme Court Could Decide Whether Your Vote Will Count.” The Washington Post. WP Company, October 2, 2017. https://www.washingtonpost.com/graphics/2017/politics/courts-law/gerrymander/.

[18] Stephanopoulos, Nicholas O. and McGhee, Eric M. (2015) “Partisan Gerrymandering and the Efficiency Gap,” University of Chicago Law Review: Vol. 82 : Iss. 2 , Article 4.

[19] Kean, Sam. “The Flaw in America’s ‘Holy Grail’ Against Gerrymandering.” The Atlantic. Atlantic Media Company, January 26, 2018. https://www.theatlantic.com/science/archive/2018/01/efficiency-gap-gerrymandering/551492/.

[20] Stephanopoulos and McGhee, “Partisan Gerrymandering and the Efficiency Gap,” 838.

[21] 130 Harv. L. Review. 1954 (2017).

Photo Credit: NPR

0 comments on “The Courts’ Role in Political Gerrymandering

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s

%d bloggers like this: